Aims of Education

Saturday January 11, 2014

Bret Victor put up his links for 2013, and one of them particularly caught my eye: Why education is so difficult and contentious, by Kieran Egan, which says that there are three conflicting goals of education. This reminded me of a paper I wrote back when I was getting my master of arts in teaching. I was able to find the paper, and sure enough I had been responding to related writing also by Egan. The difficulty with identifying the goal of education, I think, is that it's ultimately a pretty big question. What is the meaning of life? Why are we here? In my paper I tried to move toward articulating a coherent goal of education. I think the paper did not really succeed completely, but it was a step. Here it is, exactly as it was in 2006.


The Aim of Education

Man is a tame or civilized animal ; nevertheless he requires proper instruction and a fortunate nature, and then of all animals he becomes the most divine and most civilized ; but if insufficiently or ill educated, he becomes the savagest of earthly creatures. Wherefore the legislator ought not to allow the education of children to become a secondary or accidental matter. (Plato, quoted from Laws in Frank, 1947, p. 291)

The ideal aim of education is creation of power of self-control. (Dewey, 1938/1997, p. 64)

The safest general characterization of the [Western] philosophical tradition is that it consists of a series of footnotes to Plato. (Whitehead, 1929/1978, p. 39)

Education as an institution, and particularly our typically requisite kindergarten through twelfth grade, is largely accepted as a necessary and good thing. The mission of the U.S. Department of Education includes “assuring access to equal educational opportunity for every individual” and promoting “improvements in the quality and usefulness of education” (Department of Education Organization Act, 1979). It does not specify, however, what use it is that education should have. This ambiguity of purpose can cloud discussions about education. To evaluate how well a system achieves its goals, it must first be agreed what the goals are.

Several considerations should inform a discussion of education’s purpose. First there is the question of how many such purposes there may be. If there are multiple objectives then in order for education to succeed they must be compatible. Second, philosophy and pedagogy must remain clearly differentiated. An aim of education is not the same thing as a pedagogy.

The underlying question of education’s fundamental aim has unfortunately been neglected and misunderstood. Students ask why they have to go to school, and teachers should have a good answer. This paper considers the work of educational theorists’ in order to identify a consistent philosophy of education.

Egan (1997) considers the modern school as developing contemporaneously with the modern hospital and prison. Concerning prisons, he asserts that they have in the West “two aims – to punish and to rehabilitate,” and that the incompatibility of these aims leads to difficulties with the system’s implementation (p. 10). However, it could also be said that the single aim of the modern prison is to reduce crime, in which case there is no conflict in the ends but only in the means. Alternatively, it could be said that the aim of the prison is simply to house certain individuals away from the general population, for reasons and durations determined by other systems. It is important to articulate goals at an appropriate level of specificity.

Another modification to Egan’s aims for prisons would be to classify rehabilitation as punishment, in which case there is one goal and it is punishment, or alternatively that punishments contribute to the one goal of rehabilitation. Either argument, if accepted, collapses Egan’s two aims to just one and eliminates the alleged conflict. If two goals are truly distinct, it is important to establish this clearly.

After prisons, Egan goes on to construct his dilemma for education, saying that the modern school has not two but three conflicting aims. The first of these is socialization, “the homogenization of children” and the production of “a skilled workforce of good citizens” (p. 11). The second aim is labeled Platonic and focuses on “learning those forms of knowledge that would give students a privileged, rational view of reality” (p. 13). Egan attributes the third aim to Rousseau, with “focus on fulfilling the individual potential of each student” in accordance with “the nature of students’ development, learning, and motivation” (p. 15-16). After arguing the incompatibility of these three, Egan suggests a fourth of his own, sketching a sort of Vygotskyan recapitulation theory.

There are several problems with Egan’s taxonomy. Prime among these is a forced mischaracterization of Plato, with whom Egan groups E. D. Hirsch. Even in Egan’s own words, Plato hoped for students to acquire “the ability to reflect on ideas, to pull them this way and that,” not only to acquire an inert body of knowledge (p. 13). Plato and Hirsch may be similar in as much as they recommend a curriculum, but they have very different aims. Hirsch’s ideas clearly fall in Egan’s first category of socialization – his concern is with transmitting a homogenizing “cultural literacy” in order to ensure, for example, a “common reader” (Hirsch, 1987).

Plato’s goals for education are being confused with his pedagogy in Egan’s interpretation. The aims should be considered independent of the nature or effectiveness of the curriculum. Regarding his underlying philosophy of education, scholars of The Republic have noted that Plato was intensely aware of the importance of the environment in the development of individuals, and that since the uncultivated environment is often imperfect, it “can be counteracted only by creating a power for good as penetrating, as unconscious, and as universal; and to do this is the true function of a public system of education" (McClintock, 1880/1968, p. 7). Bosanquet offers that Plato’s school is “the space and atmosphere needed for the human plant to throw out its branches and flowers in their proper shape,” which sounds very much like Egan’s third category (1900, p. 12).

Indeed, Egan’s second, “Platonic” category is a phantom, on the one hand aggrandizing socialization and on the other trivializing the developmental goals shared by Plato and Rousseau alike. Egan shares these goals as well, and the “new idea” he offers is pedagogical, a different route but not a different destination. Egan notes that Rousseau saw his work as “a kind of supplement to The Republic,” and upon examination it is clear that there is, beyond pedagogy, no underlying conflict between Plato and the theorists of Rousseau’s tradition (p. 15).

After clarification of Egan’s four aims there are only two. The first is the expansion of the socialization category to include the transmittance of any inert knowledge, social or otherwise. The important note here is that transmittance of knowledge as a goal is different from the use of transmittance of knowledge to achieve other goals. This goal of transmittance is very specific. It is the goal of Hirsch, the philosophy of Thorndike, the Lockean model of “the child as empty vessel or blank slate” (Lillard, 2005, p. 9).

The second category of aim is that of Rousseau, Plato, and Egan, which has yet to be fully articulated. The lack of explicit language about this alternative fundamental aim means that in some sense “educators must establish new goals for learning” (Grabinger, p. 667). This process can begin with a review of the major relevant educational theorists starting, as Egan indicates, with the work of John Dewey.

Dewey, “the man acknowledged to be the pre-eminent educational theorist of the twentieth century,” has conspicuously little to say about fundamental aims in his Experience and Education (1938/1997). It reflects the characteristic neglect of the issue that there is so little in this work explicitly addressing it. One might think the reason for this is that it is taken for granted, as a closed question, but it is then a bit surprising when Dewey explicitly claims that "The ideal aim of education is creation of power of self-control" (p. 64).

This unexpected announcement comes in a discussion of Dewey’s notions of social control and the true nature of freedom as freedom of thought, not freedom of action. He argues that thinking is "a postponement of immediate action" (p. 64). Much more recent evolutionary theory such as that espoused by Devlin suggests that "off-line thinking," thought not connected to physical action, is a key factor differentiating humans from other animals (2000).

Other more recent educational theorists have echoed Dewey more or less subtly, as illustrated for example in the title of Bandura’s 1997 Self-Efficacy: The Exercise of Control. It was also Bandura who said that “self-reflection is the most uniquely human characteristic,” (qtd. in Pajares) aligning with Rousseau’s naturalism in the modern theory of Devlin and others. This focus on self-control as the product of education, connected as it is to evolutionary psychology, can then be viewed as a result of following Rousseau’s advice to “fix your eye on nature [and] follow the path traced by her” (qtd. in Egan, p. 16). Piaget said that scientific knowledge is “drawn in large part from common sense,” referring to his fundamental hypothesis of genetic epistemology, “that there is a parallelism between the progress made in the logical and rational organization of knowledge and the corresponding formative psychological processes.” (1968) This view of knowledge implies that anything one might learn is in some sense a result of the nature of humanity – an interesting formalization of the view that education makes us “more human.”

The two goals then can be contrasted as external versus internal. The first goal, previously called socialization, is to transmit external knowledge into the student, enforcing social rules, for example, from the outside. The second goal, of Rousseau, Dewey, and the rest, is to develop the student’s natural internal mental faculties. One might question the extent to which these goals are incompatible, or, if one were Hirsch, whether the second goal is realistically possible, meaningful, or adequate.

Dr. Maria Montessori experimentally developed a system of education that focuses on the work of students, with minimal transmittance in the usual sense of moving information from teacher or textbook into the student. She observed that in the proper environment discipline “sprang up spontaneously” and that from a student body of children judged passive or domineering, good or bad, “there remain[ed] only one kind of child” (1967, p. 202). She called this phenomenon “normalization,” and characterized its discovery as “the most important single result of [her] whole work” (p. 204). In as much as the goal of Hirsch is a behaviorist goal, concerned with instilling good (socially acceptable, beneficial, hard-working) behavior in students, Montessori provides empirical observations that such behavior can arise from students themselves, if the school setting is appropriately constructed. Plato’s interpreters would agree that in the “proper space and atmosphere” emerges “this divine humanity which is in the truest sense the self” (Bosanquet, 1900, p. 12; McClintock, 1880/1968, p. 22).

Our faith in human nature can extend beyond behavior of this kind, and in particular to language. Human children learn to speak and understand their native language without being explicitly taught – an often neglected marvel. Montessori herself noticed “the many wonders of the language mechanism,” anticipating in some ways the modern linguistics often identified with Noam Chomsky, that “there is something special about the human mind that equips it to acquire language” (Montessori, 1967, p. 116; O'Grady, Archibald, Aronoff, & Rees-Miller, 2005, p. 390). In this view, language is not learned only from external sources, but is to a degree inborn in all humans as a “Universal Grammar.” This theory is supported by a number of arguments, as well as the apparent existence of a critical period for language learning (O'Grady, Archibald, Aronoff, & Rees-Miller, 2005).

One’s native language is typically learned before schooling begins, but the nativist idea extends beyond language. For example, the principal claim of Devlin’s The Math Gene is that “the feature of our brain that enables us to use language is the same feature that makes it possible for us to do mathematics” (p. 70). Since everyone has the capacity for language, everyone has the capacity for mathematics – a traditional bastion of education. The reason people appear to vary so much more in mathematical fluency than in linguistic fluency is then a combination of the differences in environments that people are exposed to and the unnatural forms that are imposed by traditional education on mathematics.

At least in these three areas – behavior, language, and mathematics – theory and research support the view that they are natural human abilities and so are definitely developed in accordance with the second or naturalist goal for education. Generalizing broadly, it can be said that anything humans do, no matter how far removed from the struggle for survival, is by definition a naturally human behavior. In this way anything one might want to transmit to a student was produced by someone, and could also be produced by the student. There is no real conflict between “natural” and “school” capabilities; the second goal can achieve the aims of the first as well.

The converse, that inculcation of knowledge should develop the mental faculties of the student, is not so clear, and in fact it seems not to be true in general. Research indicates that “knowledge acquired in abstract circumstances without direct relevance to the needs of learners is not readily available for application or transfer to novel situations” (Grabinger). It seems that learning many facts or examples does not always lead to mental generalized concepts or what Beers and others call metacognitive skills. As Beers asked a teacher who had just spent a class explaining one short story to her class, “what did you show them that they could use with another story?” (Beers, 51)

Standardized tests provide a good illustration of this point. Although of course such tests vary in quality, test-takers with advanced cognitive skills provided even meager content exposure can generally be expected to test well. Those with extensive externally collected content knowledge may have positive results on the relevant tests, but will not necessarily develop cognitive skills in the process of internalizing this data. Their knowledge is not a transferable, applicable, and hence not a useful, thing. So while well-written standardized tests may provide a rough measure of cognitive ability, they encourage or at least allow the test-specific alternative.

Important mental skills are not served well by this first goal. As Grabinger reports, there is a difference between intentional and incidental learning (p. 672). Hirsch’s own 1898 dissertation research showed that a teacher’s instruction in one specific task did not help students perform other related tasks. Hirsch concluded that the problem was with the human mind rather than with the nature of the instruction or evaluation. The Deweyan goal for education provides a necessary alternative to this bleak outlook.

Jerome Bruner "take[s] as perhaps the most general objective of education that it cultivate excellence" and explains that this goal means "helping each student achieve his [or her] optimum intellectual development" (1960/1977, p. 9). What is meant by "excellence" or "optimum intellectual development" is not necessarily well-defined. Firstly, "optimum" may imply a stopping point. This language can however be alternatively understood to not contradict the common sentiment that one should always "desire to go on learning," so that it is this process of learning that proceeds optimally rather than merely reaching an optimal level (Dewey, 1938/1997, p. 48). Secondly, specifying each student’s optimum begs the question of how much students might vary and how this should be taken into consideration.

Since education cannot very well affect the genetic nature of students, one would hope that the natural endowments of students would not vary too wildly, and this appears to be the case. The three examples above, most notably the cognitive capability for mathematics, are human universals. Humans are genetically more similar than different, and the degree to which internal characteristics appear depends largely on the outside environment (Ridley, 2003). Across many fields, “the preponderance of psychological evidence indicates that experts are made, not born” (Ross, 2006).

Having analyzed the developmental aim of education, some consideration of how it may affect the substance of education is in order. Neither category of goal specifies a particular classroom, content, pedagogy, and so forth, but the second goal does not even specify that there might be a fixed curriculum at all. However, neither does it preclude fixed content or systems of instruction – in fact all the major theorists demand structure of some kind in education (eg. Dewey, Montessori). While it is not specified that schools should include a fixed list of disciplines for study, the second goal certainly allows for them, and provides an overarching principle for organizing and motivating their instruction. Considering the example of language, we see that children learn to speak and understand through immersion in speech communities in which they are free to participate fully – this can provide a model for what we call “learning communities.” Schools provide communities that might not be available elsewhere, identified by rigorous, disciplined thought, where teachers should provide examples of the appropriate fluencies.

The educational goal of developing students’ intellectual abilities is well-founded in this analysis. Students possess natural capabilities that may be brought out by education, and in fact anything that might be taught can be so developed naturally. It is a more robust goal as compared to the transmittance of knowledge alone, since it can effectively encourage the other while the reverse is questionable. It is a goal that can benefit all students, and it is the goal advocated, explicitly or not, by nearly all modern philosophers of education. Arriving at this goal provides a solid foundation from which to build educational programs and evaluate existing systems, but it is clearly a starting and not a finishing point. Important questions of what intellectual faculties are and how they can be developed remain, only hinted at herein. As with all things, it is important to identify and understand the questions before one can reasonably hope to find answers.

We are all aware, probably, that the word “school” is derived from a Greek word meaning “leisure.” This conception of “leisure” is one of the greatest ideas that the Greeks have left us. It is not that of amusement or holiday-making. It is opposed both to this and to the pressure of bread-winning industry, and indicates, as it were, the space and atmosphere needed for the human plant to throw out its branches and flowers in their proper shape. “To have leisure for” any occupation, was to devote yourself to it freely, because your mind demanded it ; to make it, as it were, your hobby. It does not imply useless work, but it implies work done for the love of it. In the modern world leisure is a hard thing to get ; and yet, wherever a mind is really and truly growing, the spirit of leisure is there. It is worth thinking of, how far in education the idea of the growth of a mind can be made the central point, so that the things which are considered worth teaching may really have time to sink into and to nourish the whole human being, morally and intellectually alike. (Bosanquet, 1900, p. 11-12)


References


This post was originally hosted elsewhere.